Because Peter Klevius - whose EMAH solved* "consciousness, the biggest mystery ever" 1990-94* - can't get the Nobel prize due to "anonymity" and "islamophobia" (i.e. defense of Human Rights) it should be given to the craniopagus twins Krista and Tatiana Hogan who proved him right!
* The core of which is the 'stone example' (see below) published in Demand for Resources 1992 but written 1990 and presented for G. H. von Wright (Wittgenstein's successor at Cambridge) 1991, and letter about EMAH (the Even More Astonishing Hypothesis) to Francis Crick at Salk 1994, after having been rejected from a main philosophical magazine due to it being 'too technical', and from a main neurological magazine due to it being 'too philosophical'. Peter Klevius' writing about EMAH was described by the Finnish neuroscientist, professor J. Juurmaa as: 'Peter Kleviuksen ajatuksen kulku on ilmavan lennokas ja samalla iskevän ytimekäs', which translated to English would mean something like: 'Peter Klevius' flow of thought is airily wide-ranging and at the same time strikingly pithy'. This he wrote in a long letter answering Peter Klevius' question about EMAH and the effects on the visual cortex on individuals who have been blind from birth. This inquiry was part of Peter Klevius' check up of his already published EMAH theory, so to get a qualified confirmation that the "visual cortex" in born blind people is fully employed with other tasks than vision. Juurmaa's description of Peter Klevius is in line with philosopher Georg Henrik von Wright's 1980 assessment, and perhaps more importantly beneficial when assessing AI/deep learning etc. Dear reader, this "bragging" and self-naming is only for you, i.e. to understand that you may have some reason to take this text more seriously than "the usual influencer", and to rather connect it to a name than to an 'I'. After all, Peter Klevius is almost invisible in the topics he has some expertice on. Why isn't he at least equally cited as ordinary scientists (see answer below)?
Krista and Tatiana Hogan constitute the perfect follow up to Peter Klevius' stone example from 1990-92 (see below), because when they 'talk inside their head with each other' that can only happen in their connected thalamuses, not in their disconnected cortices.
In
all other aspects they are separate individuals and personalities -
except of course for that part of the cranium that keeps them together,
and the entangled blood vessels and nerves that hindered separation.
Krista's and Tatiana's brains have a unique thalamic bridge connection
which proves Peter Klevius' 1994 theory EMAH (the Even More Astonishing
Hypothesis - which alludes to Francis Crick's book The Astonishing
Hypothesis) according to which "consciousness" resides in the thalamus -
not in the cortex, although what plays out in the thalamic "display"
triggers association patterns in the cortex which are reflected in new
thalamic patterns. According to Peter Klevius, people with split brain
halves appear as having two separate "minds" simply because each half
only connects to the thalamus and not via the corpus callosum directly
to the other half of the cortex, resulting in two separate association
patterns in each half which then mix with the other half in the thalamus
which exactly explains e.g. that these people may verbalise with one
side but not the other although the other side also understands it but
without verbalising it. However, while Tatiana and Krista Hogan share
only a communication bridge between their thalamuses the result is
exactly the same, i.e. that they "understand" each other, but from two
different patterns of associations, just like people with split brain
sharing the same thalamus. As they can "talk" with each other "inside
their head", this means the "talking" happens only in their thalamuses,
because if they should have access to the other's cortex they would feel
talking to themselves, i.e. they would be one person with one
personality.
Peter
Klevius' EMAH (the Even More Astonishing Hypothesis) 1994. The dotted
lines schematically describe the cortico-thalamic connections.
The unconnected white dots symbolise potential (nearest) connections to for the time being existing association pattern(s).
Neuronal connections and spikes in the cortex are of no interest when studying consciousness, because it resides in the thalamus. And although the thalamus doesn't represent your life history like the cortex does, it is the only display you have to your "inner world" and the only camera to your "outer world". The cortex is always the latest state of knowledge or configuration on which known and new data reflect from the thalamus. Although the thalamus "knows nothing" (much like your computer display) without it you wouldn't have access to your knowledge. Cortico-thalamic communication (e.g. thinking) is a continuous streaming where association patterns in the cortex reflect in thalamus which then reflects them back in a slightly altered way - i.e. based on but not exactly as the previous pattern, which again stimulates the next reflection from the cortex. This internal communication may then be added by external perceptions (incl. from the body).
We humans are chordates in which the thalamus evolved. We are also a special type of primates called Homo (e.g. Homo floresiensis) and our brain evolution accelerated at the beat of recent (<4 Ma) climate changes which repeatedly affected sea level. See https://peterklevius.blogspot.com/2023/01/how-pliocene-pleistocene-panama-isthmus.html
Why Peter Klevius?!
Partly
because of his particular life that has freed him from usual scientific
bias within an academic career. And partly because he has been lucky
(or unlucky) to have had extremely intelligent parents, father was,
among other things, one of Sweden's best chess player ever (won the
Gothenburg chess championship many times over more than four decades
despite playing more for fun and for the entertainment of the spectators
than for winning), and Peter Klevius half sister (same mother) won
IBM's talent contest with IQ 167. Add to this Peter Klevius lifelong
spending of time on free research on evolution and what it means to be a
human. And because of the anonymity obscurity "problem" - partly
imposed by reactionary attitudes - Peter Klevius' works aren't known by
many enough, although Wittgenstein's successor at Cambridge, von Wright,
already 1980 gave him high written credit for original
philosophical/scientific analysis on evolution and methologies , which
also led to the first paid article on a new approach to science and
evolution, and published 1981. The other part is that Peter Klevius bias
free analysis always gives anomalous results vs existing paradigms
(also compare Peter Klevius' analysis which places our evolution in SE
Asia, and the analysis of sex segregation which reveals that only
heterosexual attraction can work as an analytical tool for analyzing
relations between the sexes and Human Rights. Moreover, according to
Peter Klevius, only a full commitment to the negative (basic) Universal
Human Rights (Art. 2, 1948) can make all of us fully part of a "human
community" - unlike "monotheistic" religions which always cut out the
chosen ones from the "infidels", more or less, in one way or another.
Peter
Klevius feels almost embarrassed because the "hard problem of
consciousness" turned out to be self evident when using the EMAH model
which hones away biased concepts that muddle the view. However, due to
previous lack of interest in thalamus there are still today only limited
data available although the interest in thalanus has increased recently
(thanks to Peter Klevius bombardment on the web since 2003 with his 30
year old EMAH analysis?).
Neurological background
Apart
from the speed* problem EMAH also explains why there's almost
negligible difference in the brain's need of energy no matter how hard
we think.
* What has also been
"puzzling" for brain research (and therefore rarely properly mentioned,
or just talked away) is that reaction time seems to exceed the brain's
own speed limit. However, this is self-evident in EMAH because awareness
is already in the thalamus, and only those processes which need
additional contact with the cortex are slightly delayed in comparison.
The importance of accounting for the thalamus when theorising about cortical contributions to human cognition.
High-order
thalamic nuclei, such as the mediatorship thalamus, is the core of
cognition. However, due to the old 'just a simple relay station'
attitude against thalamus, paired with a strong defence for the
indefensible anthropocentric mentalist fantasies about linguistic
concepts such as 'soul', 'self' etc., little effort has been made to
really understand the function of the most obvious candidate as an
interactive display mediating between incoming signals from the senses
(incl. body signals) as well as from the cortex. The thalamus is ideally
positioned in the midst of the head between the brainstem and the
cortex.
The phase of both ongoing mediodorsal thalamic and
prefrontal low-frequency activity are predictive of perceptual
performance. Mediodorsal thalamic activity mediates prefrontal
contributions to perceptual performance. These findings support Peter
Klevius EMAH model (1992, and reported to Francis Crick 1994 - although
not sure if he read it despite confirmation letter from Salk Institute)
that thalamocortical interactions predict perceptual performance
displayed in thalamus as a continuous and seamless flow of new "now"
awareness, much like a frameless video.
Your brain doesn't write
memories - it deletes them by constantly updating/adapting your brain.
The default mode is when the brain is in equilibrium with incoming
signals, i.e. no new information to delete. Your brain adapts to
whatever you experience.
"Consciousness" is your thalamus'
adaptation to what your bodily sensations mean in relation to what is
going on around you in the world as well as in the cortex. Learning and
memory, language and culture are linguistic add-ons to create the mix of
"conscious" feeling, which is of course material, because what else
could it be.
Mentalism
Mentalism
is the lack of understanding that even language is physical. Although
ghosts or gods don't exist, the word 'ghost' and 'god', like the word
'stone', are physical realities. Without neurons no words, thought or
uttered. And although mentalists (like everybody else) have no clue
about any difference between concepts like "sensory inputs" and mental
"reasoning", they anyway use such a divide. Reasoning is equally verbal
and physical as talking loudly. Same with non-verbal reactions. A cat's
reasoning before jumping on a mouse is the same as when it asks for
going out. It's a linguistic "abstract" fantasy trap by mentalists to
divide memory in abstract ("immaterial") concepts and material
sensations or images.
If I utter or write 'ghost' then it
becomes operational when adapted/understood by someone. What mentalists
think is mental, is simply words that, for no particular reason, are
lumped in a language category labelled "mental".
Although EMAH
focuses on the thalamus, i.e. vertebrates, the same applies to the
mushroom body in invertebrates which is also able to instantly combine
information from the internal body as well as from the environment -
even the nerve ring of starfish fulfils this task. According to Peter
Klevius (1992), brain evolution not only started as a rudimentary
olfactory organ, but is in fact still to be seen as the main brain
notwithstanding its name and that it's limited to a tiny part of the
human brain in conventional neurological descriptions. A long forgotten
smell from one's childhood, if felt as an adult ignites the whole brain
in an overwhelming flood of associations. And the reason why olfactory
connects differently than other perceptions is simply because it was
first in line in evolution of the vertebrate brain. So even though we
have lost much of our smell capacity, there's no need to limit the
olfactory to smell. The nose is a smell organ while the olfactory organ
is so much more.
According to EMAH, Thalamus is the action centre
while cortex is the mostly fixed "storage" against which the world is
surveyed/synchronized. Cortex hence is the updatable "film" on which its
subset thalamus projects incoming signal patterns from the "outer"
environment incl. the body as well as responses from the cortex itself -
new information from the thalamus as well as what we call "thinking",
which simply means the exchange of signals initiated by the thalamus,
i.e. reciprocal cortico-cortical interactions.
The main structure from the starfish to the human brain is similarly logical, i.e. an organism's command centre is always optimally located.
While
a starfish lacks a centralized brain, it has a nerve ring around the
mouth and a radial nerve running along the ambulacral region of each arm
parallel to the radial canal. The peripheral nerve system consists of
two nerve nets: a sensory system in the epidermis and a motor system in
the lining of the coelomic cavity. Neurons passing through the dermis
connect the two. The ring nerves and radial nerves have sensory and
motor components and coordinate the starfish's balance and directional
systems. The sensory component receives input from the sensory organs
while the motor nerves control the tube feet and musculature. The
starfish does not have the capacity to plan its actions. If one arm
detects an attractive odour, it becomes dominant and temporarily
over-rides the other arms to initiate movement towards the prey. The
mechanism for this is not fully understood.
Inhibitory
interneurons, rather than relay neurons make up most of the nuclei of
the thalamus. These neurons do not project into the cortex but instead
project into the other nuclei, modulating their activity. This is how
thalamus distributes signals in accordance with incoming signals and
reflections from the cortex. Mainly the pulvinar part of the dorsal
thalamus is focused on when it comes to reasoning etc. Although the
pulvinar is usually grouped as one of the lateral thalamic nuclei in
rodents and carnivores, it stands as an independent complex in primates.
Each pulvinar nucleus has its own set of cortical connections, which
participate in reciprocal cortico-cortical interactions. Unilateral
lesions of the pulvinar result in a contralateral neglect syndrome
resembling that resulting from lesions of the posterior parietal cortex.
This again emphasizes the "dictatorship" of the thalamus.
The real "mystery of consciousness" is why the self-evident answer has been stubbornly avoided despite being presented in countless writings, talks and on the webb - even including a letter to Francis Crick in 1994.
The
reason is of course segregation used as a social and political power
tool. However, the greatness of Tatiana and Krista is precisely that
they have showed the world that total de-segregation works without loss
of individual personality. Whereas the majority of two separate twins
quarrelling is simply due to misunderstanding, Tatiana and Krista avoid
this because they can always see the rationality of whatever happens to
be at stake in their head. The thought process happens in their
connected thalamuses, not in their cortex which only reflects their
personality. In other words, what Tatiana's cortex delivers to the
thalamic display is different from what Krista's dito delivers, but in
the bridged thalamuses everything is processed as one. Their thoughts
are equally well synchronized as how they master synchronizing their
four arms and legs.
As EMAH has showed, "consciousness", i.e.
awareness, is a two-dimensional 'now'* that resides in thalamus where it
functions as a sub-set of association patterns in the cortex, always
changing due to "outer" perceptions and "inner" feedbacks from how the
corresponding association networks in the cortex happen to fit the
situation. Association pattern in the thalamus ought to be seen as a
small local subset of the global network in the brain.
*
I.e. a continuous flow of changing "nows" without history or future.
Like a seamless/frameless/seamless/f video camera where the viewer, i.e.
the brain, synchronizes/updates itself in a similarly
seamless/frameless way.
There's no "immaterial
intellect" or "material intellect" division. This thinking is a dinosaur
from the past and reflects Western unfounded belief in supra-natural
phenomenon, of which "monotheisms" - to an extent that even spelling
correctors don't know the plural form of it although there are at least
four main "monotheist" branches (Zoroastrianism, Judaism, Christianism
and its late coming cousin islamism plus a multitude of opposing
variants.
The Even More Astonishing Hypothesis (EMAH) expands AI from human-centrism* - but not from existence-centrism*.
*
Human-centrism is the dividing of the world in "human" and "non-human".
An example is humans bragging about humans which makes no sense due to
the lack of any reference outside "humans". Which "non-human" would be
able to evaluate such a claim? We humans can only brag among ourselves,
which is equally meaningless as saying that this particular set is the
best of this particular set.
EMAH sees everything as the
latest adaptation in an arbitrarily chosen (local) global set which is
in equilibrium with an other (local) global set via an interface ('now')
working as a subset.
There's no time lag in adaptation because
it's synonymous with 'now'. In conventional language use one could say
that 'adaptation', 'now' and understanding are the same.
Words
like "mind", "memory", "history", "future", "abstract", "physical", and
"understanding" cannot be conventionally used in explaining EMAH.
"mind" implies something (Homunculus paradox) that talks with itself, which is impossible
"memory" implies a possibility to "go back" which is impossible
"understanding" implies a state of "not understanding" which is an oxymoron
"history" or "future" do not exist in EMAH because there can only be a 'now' which is the latest 'state'.
"abstract or physical" is a division that lacks meaning in EMAH
The
word 'artificial' in AI seems to imply made by humans but not human,
but instead does the very opposite, i.e. outlines separate rooms for
'human intelligence' and 'human made intelligence' where there cannot be
such a division. This division has a long history and contains concepts
such as e.g. soul, mind, etc.
Algorithm AI and none-algorithm AI
Algorithms
are useful but contain human bias. For a non-biased exploration of a
certain topic we therefore need an interface without algorithms.
General statements in conventional AI vs EMAH:
Cameras don't lie - pictures do.
'Intelligent
agents' are any device that perceives its environment and takes actions
that maximize its chance of success at some goal.
EMAH: There's
no room for "agency" in an EMAH interface. And "success" is an
algorithm, i.e. defined. EMAH lacks algorithms and is therefore free to
explore without bias - like a camera.
There are endless amounts
of possible EMAH interfaces - like e.g. a mounted video camera filming
waves. No matter if you watch the display in real time or later, the
only thing you get is the latest 'now' (frame). And the only way you can
"understand" every consecutive 'now' is as the latest changes piled on a
previously "known" state.
It's said that as machines become
increasingly capable, mental facilities once thought to require
intelligence are constantly removed from the definition.
EMAH:
'Intelligence' here seems to imply either there's some undefined point
where it becomes human, or there's no such point. And of course there's
no other point than the previously mentioned human selfishness.
A state that adapts to its environment
state- now
adapts- always the sum of inputs/always "up to date"
environment- inputs (change)
example- a light switch - or millions in a changing on/off state pattern
Some objections to prevailing understanding of "consciousness"
Do
keep in mind that the verbal is physiological and the
"non-physiological" only exists as a, in this respect, meaningless but
conflating verbal expression, just like e.g. 'ghost' and 'god'.
Consciousness is neural events occurring not within the brain, but in the thalamus.
There are no qualia.
Access
consciousness, as opposed to phenomenal consciousness, is said to be
the phenomenon whereby information in our minds is accessible for verbal
report, reasoning, and the control of behavior. So, according to this
view, when we perceive, information about what we perceive is access
conscious; when we introspect, information about our thoughts is access
conscious; when we remember, information about the past is access
conscious, and so on. EMAH disputes the validity of this distinction.
P-consciousness
is said to be simply raw experience: it is moving, colored forms,
sounds, sensations, emotions and feelings with our bodies and responses
at the centre. These experiences, considered independently of any impact
on behavior, and are called qualia. EMAH object to this view because
"qualia" is both an undefinable word as well as a linguistic
categorization with no place in the brain. Brains don't do "categories".
The very core of EMAH is to remove "folk language" concepts* from the analysis. A camera never lies but pictures do. The camera doesn't see qualia.
The complexity of the
neural network in the brain of a newborn is there to be synchronized
with the individual's coming experiences. So early on a lot happens
while later in life only minor changes occur.
David Chalmers has
argued that A-consciousness can in principle be understood in
mechanistic terms, but that understanding P-consciousness is much more
challenging: he calls this the hard problem of consciousness. However,
the stone example (1992) proves that 1) observation and understanding
are the same and that 2) there's no qualitative difference between
seeing, hearing, smelling etc. and that 3) what is called understanding
as opposed to observation is in fact just retrospection in the latest
state - as is any "new understanding", e.g. when in the stone example it
turns out to be made of paper mache.
Basics of "consciousness".
There's
no other difference between the "consciousness" of a stone in a stream
of water and the "consciousness" of a human being, except for the
stone's lack of origo (the stone is adapting mainly on its surface) and
lack of language. What often misleads us is our self inflicted admiring
of our own inability to grasp the complexity of the neural network in
our brain - but not the complexity of a stone and its interaction with
its environment. Nor do most people seem to realize that language is
capable of empty oxymorons used as facts of the brain. Or perhaps they
just love this feature of language as a magician loves his tools and
tricks. And as we all know, we pay for magicians to cheat us.
1 There are no "memories" or "history" - only the most recent state.
This state is constantly changing (evolving).
These changes are random inputs - because non-random inputs wouldn't change the state.
The real "hard problem" of "consciousness" ("consciousness" originally meant 'knowing with').
The
hard problem, i.e. phenomenal consciousness, may, according to
Chalmers, be distinguished from the soft problem", i.e. access
consciousness. In EMAH, like in Dennett, there's no need for such a
divide.
2 The overall state (the cortex) is fixed until it gets changes from the thalamus.
Random inputs will be allocated into the existing state in accordance with its actual focus.
Focus
= the thalamic sub-state ("consciousness") that is dependent on the
actual association pattern in the cortex. Changes could come from cortex
in interaction with other association patterns or from outside the
brain, i.e. from the opposite direction in the thalamic display.
Actual focus = e.g. "awareness"/to be "conscious", which in whatever system simply means now.
System = whatever that changes.
The language problem (compare Donald Duck in the holy land of language in EMAH)
Wittgenstein called language a well functioning but hopelessly inaccurate game.
1 a neural network
2 random input to 1 causing a minor change in 1
3 1 will now be almost the same as previously except for a minor alteration caused by 2
4 next input will do the same unless it hits the previous one, in which case no reaction
5 the flow of random inputs continues
translated to EMAH and exemplified with how the brain works as a painter and a canvas
1 a canvas
2 experience painting on that canvas
3 a new canvas slightly different from the previous
4 if "painted" on a spot with the same "color" nothing changes
5
the "painter" never stops painting - but s/he is lazy so the canvas
changes very little over time - although the patterns on the canvas has
become all the time more "like" the "model"
Summary
We
(like everything else) don't "observe" or "understand" or "memorize" -
we adapt. And not only to our outer surrounding but equally to our own
body incl. our brain. Or a brick turning into grovel/sand. Or a star
turning into a supernova etc.
Is the pattern of the flying dust from what used to be a brick less or more "complex"? Or the supernova?
Although
the brain/nerve system could be seen as more complex, it's no different
from e.g. light skin that gets tanned in the sun.
EMAH is
extremely simple - yet not "simplistic". However, the culprit is what
humans are most proud about, i.e. language. By giving something one
doesn't comprehend but wants to put in a package, a name, will continue
to contain its blurred (or sometime empty) "definition". This is why
EMAH only deals with 'now' and the body/state of the "past" (erased in
the process) this 'now' continuously lands on. Of course this leads to
everything (or nothing) having "consciousness".
A brick
"remembers" a stain of paint as long as it's there - and with some
"therapeutical" investigation in a laboratory perhaps even longer. And a
stain of paint on your skin is exactly the same. However, unlike the
brick you've also got a brain that was affected by the stain. This could
be compared with a hollow brick where the paint has vanished from the
outside but submerged into the brick's "brain" so that when cutting the
brick it "remembers" it and "tells" the cutting blade about it. And for
more complexity and "sophistication", just add millions of different
colors unevenly spread.
Although the brick example of course will
be challenged by mentalists - they in turn will be refuted by the
Homunculus paradox, Wittgenstein's private language problem, etc.
Background to Peter Klevius' 'stone example' against unfounded but populist "immaterial consciousness".
This
top science isn't offered to the mediocre Nature because that PC
magazine's quality isn't good enough and Peter Klevius doesn't have the
means to get a proper Chinese translation. So Google gets it in power of
its Western hegemony - not Google's quality which due to PC and
especially its connection with the militaristic leadership of the
$-freeloader U.S. constitutes a security risk beyond comprehension.
Here's
an other example. 1957 -Swedish Arvid Carlsson was first in the world
to demonstrate that dopamine is a neurotransmitter in the brain and not
just a precursor for norepinephrine. He also discovered that lack of
dopamine causes Parkinson. However, although Israel awarded him already
1979, and Japan 1994, it was only in 2000 he got the Nobel prize and had
to share it with two others. Why? Because Swedish state supported
mentalists (what Peter Klevius calls the psycho state) have had a strong
strangle hold on research about the brain.
It's a linguistic
"abstract fantasy" trap to divide memory in abstract ("immaterial")
concepts and material sensations or images. Krista and Tatiana Hogan
constitute the perfect follow up to Peter Klevius' stone example from
1990-92, because when they 'talk inside their head with each other' that
can only happen in their connected thalamuses, not in their
disconnected cortices.
Mentalists' unproven and unreachable s.c.
"objective reality" (or "fantasy reality") stands as the basis for their
unproven idea about non-physical mental processes in the brain at the
same time as they admit that sensory inputs are physical. This view
stands in sharp opposition to idealists' who only see what the
(physical) senses bring - but honestly admit that they have nothing to
say about a "world" outside the senses - except for Berkely who called
the not reachable "god". But according to Peter Klevius'
existencecentrism, not even "god" fits in a set that can't be talked
about. Moreover, Peter Klevius is convinced that the intellectual
schizophrenia of mentalists is detrimental to Human Rights.
Peter
Klevius ontology and epistemology rests on Atheism, i.e. the lack of
monotheisms, combined with negative (basic) Human Rights, i.e. the lack
of impositions based on human characteristics, other than laws guided by
negative (basic) Human Rights. Peter Klevius is not a mentalist (see
below). Peter Klevius' analysis puts him, like Daniel Dennett, at odds
with mentalists.
Acknowledgement: The simple reason I often refer
to myself with my name in the text is because as a less known underdog
outside the conventional academic sphere (which is in fact my main
asset) there's a real chance that many will not only dismiss the author,
but more importantly, just cherry pick from my texts out of proper
context. Moreover, for me it's essential that I'm understood because
that's the only way for me and others to criticize myself. Furthermore, I
don't know about you dear reader, but although I'm fluent in three
languages, my thinking, like that of all animals, is mostly non-verbal,
meaning I have to translate it to words. This translation is for
mentalists the very obstacle to understand how the brain works.
Origins
Ultimately
the stone example and EMAH go back to Peter Klevius' correspondence
with G. H. von Wright (Wittgenstein's successor at Cambridge) 1980 and a
published and paid article 1981 about evolution and scientific
methodology 1981. However, at the time I wrote the stone example I was
puzzled by how my theory could be physiologically explained. I didn't
know about the two-way cortico-thalamic connections until 1993 when they
were outlined in Nature. The manuscript to Peter Klevius' Demand for
Resources (with the 'stone example') was in its final form presented for
G. H. von Wright (Wittgenstein's successor at Cambridge) before Daniel
Dennett's Consciousness Explained was available. Moreover, whereas Peter
Klevius' analysis at the time lacked physiological evidence for
thalanmus involvement, Dennett based his (non-mentalist) view on
available data which constituted mainly of in the 1980s so popular brain
imaging of blood flow, which gave the wrong impression that thinking
happened all over the brain, and which also encountered the speed limit
problem that was neglected by "close to the same time". Peter Klevius
analysis eloquently resolved this problem by keeping attention/awareness
in the smaller thalamus "display" while the cortex stands for the
totality of adaptations of which only a tiny part is projected on the
thalamus. So what the blood flow images show is just the history of what
the thalamus has been busy with, i.e. the association patterns thalamus
activates on the cortex.
In fact, Peter Klevius didn't even know
the existence of Dennett until many years after Peter Klevius' letter
to Francis Crick. Why Dennett is mentioned here is because he seems to
be a non-mentalist and closest to Peter Klevius analysis. However,
unlike Peter Klevius' 'stone example' where consciousness is limited to a
real time 'now' "image" of the world (i.e. no depth), Dennett compares
consciousness to an academic paper that is being developed or edited in
the hands of multiple people close to the same time, the "multiple
drafts" theory of consciousness. In this analogy, "the paper" exists
even though there is no single, unified paper. When people report on
their inner experiences, Dennett considers their reports to be more like
theorizing than like describing. These reports may be informative, he
says, but a psychologist is not to take them at face value. Dennett
describes several phenomena that show that perception is more limited
and less reliable than we perceive it to be. Dennett's views put him (as
Klevius) at odds with thinkers who say that consciousness can be
described only with reference to subjective "qualia". These "qualia"
people's (ab)use of language is the main obstacle for understanding how
the brain works and therefore also the main target for Peter Klevius
analysis, which could otherwise been much shorter. One year after
publishing Demand for Resources, Peter Klevius read in Nature about
two-way cortico-thalamic connections which immediately for him located
the stone example to the thalamus, hence overcoming earlier problems
about neural speed limits in the brain.
Short form of Peter Klevius ontology (1981, 2003): Peter Klevius would be helpless without an assisting world*.
*
Peter Klevius has no 'self' or 'private language' because all of him is
a product of his environment (incl. his body). Moreover, the world that
has shaped him is exactly his whole world. There can't be a world
"beyond" existencecentrism (see below). Same applies to the whole of
humankind. This world is constantly changing but can never exceed the
borders of existencecentrism.
And here's a longer form for those
who desperately try to misinterpret it for the sake of rescuing their
beliefs. As in the preface to my 1992 book Demand for Resources, I again
appeal for a positive reading - so to save the reader from her/his own
prejudice:
Being is ultimately only comprehensible as an
all-inclusive whole which Peter Klevius calls 'existencecentrism', i.e.
that the view from one's (or humankind's) particular origo is always
limited (otherwise we would be all seeing gods) which also excludes
"metaphysics" or if you like, integrates "metaphysics" into our
existencecentrism, i.e. into what can be said/experienced. There cannot
exist anything outside our reality because "existence" is dependent on
human minds. Trying to talk "outside" one's existencecentrism is
therefore impossible and only ends up in a navel gazing dead end of
undefinable "nothingness".
Language has overwhelmed our thinking
to an extent that often hinders or complicates the analysis of it. The
'stone example' below is meant to reveal the true nature of language as
just an adaptation among others, so to discharge it from conflating
misleading words about how organs (e.g. the brain) work. We have a
tendency to create meaningless questions because language - but not the
world - allows it. Words like 'memory', 'past', 'future' etc., have no
meaning when exploring awareness/consciousness because there's only one
valid latest 'now' at the time, just like a video where only the last
frame is relevant for viewing. If the stone in the stone example later
turns out not to be a stone, then we can no longer "remember" the
"stone" we saw before we realized it wasn't a stone.
There's no
"reality" or "things-in-themselves" outside our existencecentrism,
simply because whatever we talk about is per definition already inside.
So trying to explain something humans come up with and to demand a "god"
to answer a question that makes no sense - makes no sense. This also
means that there's no basis for questions like 'don't you believe in a
human independent reality'. A human independent "reality" is per
definition out of reach, so the question becomes an oxymoron. A human
perceived object or world can't exist if humans are forever gone. Our
world is in our mind only - where else could it possibly reside.
However, many seem to have problem letting the question go, e.g. by
stubbornly repeating the naive 'but surely the table must still be there
even if all humans are gone'. And if we pretend being an all seeing
god, then we would realize that the bird on what humans used to call a
'table' strongly disagrees while conceptualizing it perhaps as a place
for landing.
There are no colors, objects etc. in the brain, only
the imprint on the neuronal network of our adaptations with our world
incl. each other. We adapt to our surrounding just like a rock in a
continuous stream of water, or a flatworm to light. The light absorbed
by silver crystals on photographic film produces a reflection that can
only be "understood" as an image based on earlier adaptations to what is
interpreted to be in the image. An image of the stone in the 'stone
example' may be interpreted as a stone or paper mache, depending on the
knowledge of the viewer. To be able to know the world at all, there must
be a continuing identity of mind and perception. This equilibrium is
upheld by synchronizing new perceptions with the previous state of the
mind.
Mind or consciousness are physical and physiological.
Everything else is just language. It's language that makes consciousness
"mysterious". The reason many humans don't accept consciousness in e.g.
flatworms is that humans tend to drown in their oceans of neurons etc.
A
mind independent world is impossible because how could we possibly talk
about something "outside" our mind. If you, like naive "realists", say
that objects still exist even if there's not a single human left to
sense them, then ask yourself how to sense such objects without any
human existing to perform the sensing? Moreover, if an unknown force
suddenly puts universe into a state of time and space-less singularity,
then where are your objects? This latter example is of course equally
naive as the naive "realist" position, and therefore belongs to them.
Peter Klevius commenting on the misuse of widely used concepts:
* Such concepts may of course be perfectly usable in openly declared local contexts.
'A car' is equally concrete or abstract as 'the car'.
Although
earlier cosmological models of "the" universe now are accused of being
geocentric, i.e. placing Earth at the center, nothing has really changed
because "the" universe is anyway still both anthropocentric as well as
limited by our existencecentrism. Yesterday's Earth is today's "Big
Bang" (P. Klevius 1992:22).
The 'empty set' is the most
operational of all sets in that its impossible task is to keep things
from entering it, e.g. its own conceptual defining framework.
Objects, operations, and functions
Peter Klevius: Objects, operations, and functions, are all dependent on each other.
Organs of sense-
Peter Klevius: There can't be "organs of sense", because then there could also be "organs of appearances" etc. stupidities.
produce sensations out of which appearances take place-
Peter
Klevius: There's no difference between sensations and appearances.
Where would you draw such a line? "Sensations and appearances" meet in
the thalamus where they become one, i.e. 'now'.
and these come to represent something that renders objects thinkable.
Peter
Klevius: Represent what? Where was the original presentation? The "real
world" that's beyond us?! But our existencecentrism excludes us from
even talking about it - and if we do we are back to appearances.
Although
one could say that the heart is the origo of the blood flow, unlike the
nervous system that feeds the brain, the heart is part of an an
inclusive system. And the stone in the flow of water doesn't have an
origo, other than its centre of gravity.
Why are we here? This
question is senseless because it rests on the possibility of a
"nothingness" which would be impossible to define because its definition
would kill the concept as well as the question. So when Penrose says
Universe at some extremely diluted point may "forget" space and time,
then this scenario is still within our existencecentrism. Wittgenstein's
'bedrock' is Peter Klevius' existencecentrism.
Just like a stone
in the continuous flow of water adapts to its environment, similarly
the mind doesn't need to "structure" and "process" incoming data,
because it simply maps it on the existing data map. Better still, there
are no "incoming" data, only nerve reactions. And just like we make
sense of an image, similarly we make sense of other reactions.
There
is no one thing that unifies being human - except negative (basic)
Human Rights, which don't limit your sphere of love or passion, but
let's others do the same without impositions, except for what is
restricted by laws guided by these same rights.
Dear reader, don't confuse this text with nihilism because it's actually less nihilistic than mainstream views on the subject.
The
significance of Peter Klevius' stone* example from 1992, is to embed
contentious or confusing concepts into a theoretical analysis that makes
their connections to other categories more explicit. As a consequence
it will also reveal the impossibility of any effort to draw a
distinction between abstract and concrete objects because there simply
can't exist a human definition in a "reality" outside human experience.
The 'car' is equally abstract as the 'thought' about it. And the
neuronal activity we call a thought process is certainly equally
physical and physiological as photons hitting the retina or the
molecules hitting our mouth and nose, or the vibrations hitting our
ears. The fancy "elevation" of some physical/physiological events to a
"higher" status has no real foundation.
*
The reason Peter Klevius chose 'stone' instead of 'rock' is that 1) in
Swedish it's 'sten', and 2) in both Swedish and its creole descendant
English, the word sten/stone is also associated with phrases like stone
blind (literally "blind as a stone"), stone deaf, stone-cold, etc.,
which then contrasts more sharply with the 'mind'. Yet, nothing excludes
the possibility of describing a stone as equally complex as the brain.
There
are no functions without objects. A function is an operation which
needs objects to function, such as variables or other operational
"tools". You can't think about a number without its operational
function, be it functioning as a sign or a calculation. There simply
doesn't exist a naked number. Same with colors, which will always be
somehow framed.
Everything experienced is always understood,
which means that every conceptualization happens in the brain - not in
an outside "reality". The retroactive "understanding" that the stone
later turned out to be something else, is just a new understanding.
The
oxymoron 'true by definition' is limited to its definition. The
"out-of-Africa" myth, for example, rests on defining modern DNA as
representing the same locality (Africa) several hundred thousands of
years ago. And fossils are pure lottery if they can't be satisfactorily
tied to evolutionary origin. This is why Homo floresiensis on the
"wrong" side of the Wallace line, outperforms all fossils in Africa.
The stone example reveals that:
1
Recognition of a stone as matching the concept of a 'stone' is
culturally embedded in our brain as a result of adaptation (programmed
through lived experience). There is no direct understanding of a "real"
stone, only the cumulative adaptations of when to use the concept, or
how to deal with it in general - just like animals do without linguistic
concepts.
2 'Stone' is a linguistic reflection and doesn't cover
humans who are non-linguistic*. Language is an anthropocentric
operation, and therefore not applicable to non-linguistic lives or
things. This means a linguistic machine could understand a linguistic
human linguistically, whereas a non-linguistic human would not
understand a linguistic machine.
3 To see or touch a stone both need
the recognition that it is a stone. Photons from the stone or from the
ink in the world stone do exactly the same as touching the stone - which
includes hearing the word stone. And if the surface feels hard it could
still be a hollow shell. And if it feels heavy like a stone it could
still be a dirty piece of hollow gold weighing the same as an ordinary
'stone'.
* The most naive, or alternatively, the most
self-evident of value based expressions is that 'humans are special' -
but not more or less special than a billion year old stone or a flying
fruit fly. And the only way to encompass all humans as fully human is to
Atheistically and axiomatically accept it as e.g. it's stated in in the
original anti-fascist, anti-racist, anti-sexist U.N.'s Universal
Declaration of Human Rights from 1948 - which islam's biggest and most
influential organization, the Saudi based and steered O.I.C., 1990
declared not acceptable and therefore replaced it with an islamic sharia
declaration, which contrary to Art. 2 in the UDHR, imposes segregated
"rights".
First of all one needs to accept that we are by
necessity anthropocentric (and above all existencecentric). How could we
possibly not be humans? You may also benefit from learning about later
Ludwig Wittgenstein (who asked my mentor* G. H. von Wright to be his
successor at Cambridge) whose reasoning is in good harmony with Peter
Klevius EMAH theory which in turn pushes the "consciousness"/language
"problem" to its ultimate end - without embarking on simplisticism.
Unfortunately there seems to be a problematic aversion against
Wittgenstein's most important insights among many Western scholars,
probably due to the fact that Wittgenstein in his later period didn't
follow a more conventional philosophical jargon and methodology within
the discipline, but rather questioned its borders. Aversion against
Wittgenstein may also have something to do with the heavy influence of
"monotheisms"** which became widespread in the West because ot the Roman
empire. However, it also feeds into a quite appalling and racist
dismissal of non-monotheistic thought traditions. And Atheism, which is
the only possible foundation for fully adopting basic (negative) Human
Rights, is in e.g. U.S. politics etc. still almost seen as a curse. This
Western bigoted hypocrisy is easily seen in statements about
"monotheistic" religions as somehow the 'crown of sophistication' -
although stunningly disproved by history. Moreover, Kierkegaard was an
individualist, not a "communityist".
*
G. H. von Wright strongly supported P. Klevius' 1979 paper Resursbegär
(Demand for Resources) that was published 1981 as a paid article. Same
thing happened a decade later with Peter Klevius book with the same name
and published 1992 - although he thought its 'aphoristic form' could be
difficult for some readers.
** Atheist Wittgenstein's curiosity
about religion has often been wilfully misinterpreted. Wittgenstein was
also interested in other similar human entanglements such as e.g.
psychoanalysis. A telling sign is that the father of psychoanalysis,
Sigmund Freud, didn't fit in his list of people who had influenced him
the most, but included Otto Weininger, the youngster whom Freud had
dismissed and probably became complicit to what led to the vulnerable
young and depressed genius' suicide. And because Weininger's Sex and
Character was seen as misogynistic, Wittgenstein was asked how he could
like such a work. To which Wittgenstein answered that one may negate
everything in it and it's still good. Peter Klevius' thesis Pathological
Symbiosis implies the question how many young lives have been distorted
or destroyed because of psychoanalytically influenced actions. Adult
people can choose if they want to consult these modern magicians, but
have no such right when authorities decide about their children.
Our
mind consists of adaptive associations/reactions in every 'now' built
on previous ones. However, using the associations/reactions (or simply
adaptations) we call language to "explain" associations/reactions to
language, of course causes confusion. Mind is a word that can be used as
a synonym for human, and hence solely restricted to humans while
therefore also eliminating the possibility of the question: Do others
than humans have minds? Alternatively one may expand its use over the
human border and face no defensible restrictions at all. However, since
humans are trapped in our own existencecentrism we lack authority to
talk for others. What we can do though is to clean up our
anthropocentric discourse. To avoid the "consciousness mystery" one has
to clearly distinguish between single human-only bordered experience and
one that includes the totality of human existencecentrism* (see P.
Klevius 1992:21-22). This is why the question: 'Do animals have
consciousness?' is a meaningless oxymoron. Starting by declaring only
humans have "consciousness" while then blurring this concept with other
human centered concepts such as "soul", "spirit", "self" etc.,
inevitably leads to questions about animals and due conflation of the
original concept. This is no different from the slow acceptance of
evolution where still today many stubbornly keep hanging on the 'humans
are special' myth. Humans can only be special among humans. How would a
non-human possibly even know what is meant by 'humans'?
The
'Universe' is fully comprehensible for humans because the whole of it is
bordered by human existencecentrism. Humans hence rule the world by
absolute dictatorship.
The fancy idea that 'there's a physical
reality' independent of humans, I abandoned in my early teens after
reading Einstein's and Barnett's book about Universe. The concept of
'physical reality' (which implies some other perceivable "reality") is
inevitably and only contained into human language - so without humans no
"physical reality". "Reality" has no mysterious "essence" other than
what humans inject "it" with. A 'stone', a 'brick, a 'table' etc. have
no "essence" but are, like e.g. numbers, only operational, i.e. context
bound. And the only essence humans have in common is the axiomatic
"being human". Sure we can talk about it, touch, make experiments and
even agree that the Earth is still there even after Uncle Sam has
started a nuke war that eventually could accelerate and make humans
extinct. However, where would the human perceptions be stored? And even
if the CDs on Voyager somehow came in contact with what we used to call
"Aliens" - the cultural content is equally cut off as are prehistoric
'humans' (i.e. the genus) artefacts from us living humans.
In
Demand for Resources (1992) Peter Klevius pointed out the difference
between the modern use of the word existence as implying the possibility
of non-existence, and the more sensible and culturally much older and
more widespread meaning of something emerging (compare 'existere'), i.e.
not out of "nothing" or "god".
Reality is always confined within
the borders of existencecentrism. "Metaphysics" hence is (or should be)
simply the acceptance of existencecentrism. So whatever "universe",
"reality" or "spirit" is contemplated, it always resides within the
borders of existencecentrism. While existence is motion/change, the
borders of existencecentrism constitute an unchangeable relativity. No
matter what new insights are made they cannot change this because there
is no "reality" beyond existenecentrism that could be used as a
reference. The size of the "still unknown" is always infinite. On the
level of humankind this means that it cannot be assessed, compared,
evaluated etc. against other "kinds" other than by using a meaningless
"humankind" comparison.
The mentalists' love for a "mental", as opposed to physical, hiding place.
As
Peter Klevius wrote 1981, 'the meaning of life is uncertainty' - which
offers more possibilities than any narrow minded mentalist view. This
uncertainty is rich enough in itself and contrary to what mentalists
believe, mentalism not only actually limits freedom but also boosts
racism and sexism as defined in the 1948 Universal Human Rights
declaration.
And according to the stone example in EMAH there is
no in this context meaningful separation between observation and
understanding. The relation between a new observation that contradicts
an earlier one is not consciousness but can of course be titled
'understanding'. And the totality of our understanding is just the
temporal body of adaptations bordered against the future by a now. In
other words, future doesn't exist per se.
One way of helping to
understand EMAH is to think about an internally active two-way
display/monitor (thalamus in vertebrates) with ever changing "meetputs"
('nows' - i.e. stream of "images") between input and output, incl.
inputs and outputs from your brain and other parts of your body.
"Sensory information" has conventionally been seen as a specific type of
stimulus. This view is a linguistic mirage which arbitrarily
categorizes certain inputs. Although it's useful to talk about hearing,
vision etc., there's no need to make a "sensory group" which only
creates unnecessary bias when analyzing "consciousness".
Peter Klevius stone example unifies all modes of observation and communication.
If we want to break the borders of human navel-gazing we also need to clean up cross-border concepts.
In
the 1980s, while reading Jurgen Habermas' The Theory of Communicative
Action, Peter Klevius criticized his division observation and
understanding as I had always used to do in other contexts. However, my
(perhaps overly) respect for Habermas made me wondering why even he used
such a meaningless distinction.
Peter Klevius' 'stone example' in Resursbegär (Demand for Resources) from 1992 (pp 32-33, ISBN 9173288411).
The
connection between intelligence/intellect and its biological anchors
may appear problematic on several levels. This applies to the connection
between sensory impressions and abstraction. In a remark regarding
rational reconstruction, Jurgen Habermas makes a distinction between
what he calls sensory experience (observation) and communicative
experience (understanding). Against this one may argue by seeing the
thought process as consisting of parts of memory patterns and
experiences that must be understood to be meaningful at all.
sees a stone* = visual perception understood by the viewer
I see a stone = utterance understood by another person
* When the origo/viewer then kicks the "stone" it turns out to be made of paper mache, i.e. becoming a new updated adaptation.
I
presume that Habermas sees the latter example as communication due to
the reference (via language) to the original viewer's visual impression
of the stone, while I claim that this "extension" of the meaning of the
statement cannot be proven to be of a different nature than the
thought/understanding process behind the first example. This
understanding of the stone does not differ from the understanding of an
abstract symbol like e.g. a letter or a word, written or pronounced. The
statement 'I see a stone' is also a direct sensory impression which,
like the stone as an object, has no meaning if it is not understood.
Here one may then object that the word stone in contrast to the
phenomenon of seeing a stone can transfer meaning (symbolic
construction, according to Habermas). Still, I would insist that this
too is illusory and a consequence of our way of perceiving language and
Popper's third world (see below). A stone can be perceived as everything
from the printing ink in a word to an advanced symbolic construction.
It is then not a matter of a difference between observation and
understanding, but only different, unbounded levels of understanding.
Nor does the division "pure observation" and "reflective observation"
have any other than purely comparative meaning, since no delimitation
(other than the purely comparative one) can be made in a meaningful way.
Does it not matter then that the communication takes place between two
conscious, thinking beings? Certainly, Habermas and others are free to
elevate communication between individuals to a group other than the
communication the stone observer has with himself and his cultural
heritage via mirroring in the stone, but in this case this is only an
ethnocentric stance without relevance to the observation/understanding
distinction. For me, therefore, there is no fundamental difference in
the symbol combination of the sensory experience of a stone or of
Habermas text. Of course, that does not mean that I would in any way
express any form of judgement of Habermas or the stone. What it does
mean, however, is that I want to question the division
observation/understanding and thus also the division primitive/civilized
thinking (P. Klevius 1992:32-33).
To be fair, it should be said
that Haberma's exemplification is based on a completely different chain
of thought with a purpose other than the one discussed here and that I
only try to demonstrate the danger of generalizing the
observation/understanding relationship. In other contexts, it becomes
almost unnoticed transferred to a linguistic axiom (virus or bug to take
information technology as an example) which then both generates and
accumulates differences that do not exist.
In the book Evolution
of the Brain/Creation of the Self (foreword by Karl Popper) John C.
EccIe notes that: '1t is surprising how slow the growth of World 3 (K.
Popper's and J. EccIe's division of existence and experience; World I =
physical objects and states, World 2 = states of consciousness, World 3 =
knowledge in objective sense) was in the earlier tens of thousands of
years of Homo sapiens sapiens. And even today there are races of mankind
with negligible cultural creativity. Only when the societies could
provide the primary needs of shelter, food, clothing, and security were
their members able to participate effectively in cultural creativity, so
enriching World 3.'
This quote shows both Eccie's and Popper's
legitimate concern about the issue and the cultural evolutionary escape
route they use to leave the question (compare chapter Khoi, San and
Bantu in this book). It also reveals a certain, perhaps unconscious,
aversion to the idea that societies would voluntarily settle for
satisfying their "primary needs." Karl Popper has, with reason, made
himself known as the champion of freedom and herein I fully share his
attitude. Freedom (implicitly a humane and responsible freedom) is
clearly a scarce commodity in the modern state. At the same time, the
concept of freedom does not exist at all among the gatherer-hunter
cultures referred to in this book. The concept of freedom, like
diamonds, is created only under pressure (P. Klevius 1992:33).
Original EMAH as web version 2004. The theory is exactly as it was when sent to Francis Crick 1994, although the text is slightly altered, but without any changes in the theory*.
*
Already in the 1970s I had the same view as today about how the brain
works. The reason for this is twofold: Firstly, I read and scoffed at
Laing's perverted but populist view on mental illness, and secondly, I
happened to work in a mental hospital as a guard on a department for the
worst cases, where I thoroughly read everything about the 40 patients
there, and concluded that they all had become worse in their teens,
although with very different backgrounds and lives. Some of them showed
autism early in their childhood but most didn't show anything before
their teens. This led me to Arvid Carlsson and his dopamine research.
And the only reason I called my theory "the even more astonishing
hypothesis" (EMAH) was because of Crick's book 'The Astonishing
Hypothesis' which didn't astonish me at all. However, EMAH is a theory
because it is falsifiable, it fits all existing data, and it has
predicted everything that research has revealed since. Moreover, it's
not shallow but to the very point. Therefore, dear reader, if you have
doubts or if something in the theory is hard to understand because of my
incompetency as a writer, please contact me on klevius-yahoo.com
The
theory was presented for Georg Henrik von Wright (Wittgenstein's
successor at Cambridge) 1991, and 1994 sent to Francis Crick (only got a
confirmation from Salk administration so not sure if he ever read it),
and 2004 presented on the web* for the entire world.
* My EMAH page on Yahoo's Geocities was quite frequently visited for many years until Geocities was terminated.
Abstract:
Thalamus is the least discussed yet perhaps the most important piece in
the puzzle of mind, due to its central function as the main relay
station between body actions and environment. A critical assessment of
concepts such as: observation/understanding, mind/body, free will and
language reveals an inescapable awareness in the Thalamic "meetputs". In
conclusion memories hence may be better described as linguistic traps
rather than as distinct entities. The continuity model proposed in EMAH
also avoids the limitations of a "discrete packets of information"
model.
Note. In some respect the neural network of "lower"
systems such as the spinal cord and cerebellum by far outperforms the
cortex. This is because of different tasks (fast motorics and slow
adaptations) and due difference in processing. (Copyright Peter
Klevius).
Introduction
Understanding
how social behavior and its maintenance in human and other forms of
life (incl. plants etc) evolved has nothing to do with “the balance
between self interest and co-operative behavior” but all to do with
kinship and friendship. Although humans may be attributed a more chaotic
(i.e. more incalculable) "personality", they are, like life in general,
just robots (i.e. active fighters against entropy – see Demand for
Resources - on the right to be poor). Misunderstanding (or plain
ignorance of – alternatively ideological avoidance of) kinship (kin
recognition), friendship (symbiosis), and AI (robotics) pave the way for
the formulation of unnecessary, not to say construed, problems which,
in an extension, may become problematic themselves precisely because
they hinder an open access for direct problem solving (see e.g. Angels
of Antichrist – kinship vs. social state).
The Future of a "Gap" (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
Human:
What is a human being? Can the answer be found in a non-rational a
priori statement (compare e.g. the axiomatic Human Rights individual) or
in a logical analysis of the "gap" between human beings and others? The
following analysis uses an "anti-gap" approach. It also rests on the
struggle and success of research performed in the field of artificial
intelligence (AI), robotics etc.
Signal: A "signal gap" is
commonly understood as a break in the transition from input to output,
i.e., from perception to behavior. Mentalists use to fill the gap with
"mind" while behaviorists don't bother because they can't even see it.
Matter:
Berkeley never believed in matter. What you experience is what you get
and the rest is in the hands of "God" (i.e. uncertainty). This view
makes him a super-determinist without "real" matter.
Mind: The
confusing mind-body debate originates in the Cartesian dualism, which
divides the world into two different substances, which, when put
together, are assumed to make the world intelligible. However, on the
contrary, they seem to have created a new problem based on this very
assumption.
Free will: Following a mind-body world view, many
scholars prefer to regard human beings as intentional animals fuelled by
free will. It is, however, a challenging task to defend such a
philosophical standpoint. Not even Martin Luther managed to do it, but
rather transferred free will to God despite loud protests from Erasmus
and other humanists. Although Luther's thoughts in other respects have
had a tremendous influence on Western thinking, this particular angle of
view has been less emphasized.
Future: When asked about the
"really human" way of thinking, many mentalists refer to our capacity to
"calculate" the future. But is there really a future out there? All
concepts of the future seem trapped in the past. We cannot actually talk
about a certain date in the future as real future. What we do talk
about is, for example, just a date in an almanac. Although it is a good
guess that we are going to die, the basis for this reasoning always lies
in the past. The present hence is the impenetrable mirror between the
"real future" and ourselves. Consequently every our effort to approach
this future brings us back in history. Closest to future we seem to be
when we live intensely in the immediate present without even thinking
about future. As a consequence the gap between sophisticated human
planning and "instinctual" animal behavior seems less obvious. Is
primitive thinking that primitive after all?
An additional aspect of
future is that neither youth, deep freezing or a pill against ageing
will do as insurance for surviving tomorrow.
Observation and Understanding (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
If
one cannot observe something without understanding it, all our
experiences are illusions because of the eternal string of corrections
made by later experiences. What seems to be true at a particular moment
may turn out to be something else in the next, and what we call
understanding hence is merely a result of retrospection.The conventional
way of grasping the connection between sensory input and behavioral
output can be described as observation, i.e. as sensory stimulation
followed by understanding. The understanding that it is a stone, for
example, follows the observing of a stone. This understanding might in
turn produce behavior such as verbal information. To do these simple
tasks, however, the observer has to be equipped with some kind of
"knowledge," i.e., shared experience that makes him/her culturally
competent to "understand" and communicate. This understanding includes
the cultural heritage embedded in the very concept of a stone.
Categorization
belongs to the language department, which, on the brain level, is only
one among many other behavioral reactions. But due to its capability to
paraphrase itself, it has the power to confuse our view on how we
synchronize our stock of experience. When we look at a stone, our
understanding synchronizes with the accumulated inputs associated with
the concept of a stone. "It must be a stone out there because it looks
like a stone," we think. As a result of such synchronization, our brain
intends to continue on the same path and perhaps do something more (with
"intention"). For example, we might think, "Let's tell someone about
it." The logical behavior that follows can be an expression such as,
"Hey look, it's a stone out there." Thus, what we get in the end is a
concept of a stone and, after a closer look, our pattern of experience
hidden in it. If the stone, when touched, turns out to be made of paper
mache, then the previous perception is not deepened, but instead,
switched to a completely new one.
One might say that a stone in a
picture is a real stone, while the word "stone" written on a piece of
paper is not. The gap here is not due to different representations but
rather to different contexts. When one tries to equalize observation
with understanding, the conventional view of primitive and sophisticated
thinking might be put in question. We act like no more than complex
worms and the rest, such as sophistication, is only a matter of biased
views built on different stocks of experience. But a worm, just like a
computer, is more than the sum of its parts.
Therefore, meaning,
explanation and understanding are all descriptions of the same basic
principle of how we synchronize perceptions with previous experiences.
For the fetus or the newborn child, the inexperienced (unsynchronized,
or uncertainty/"god" if you prefer) part of the inside-outside
communication is considerably huge. Hence the chaotic outside world
(i.e., the lack of its patterns of meaningfulness) has to be copied in a
stream of experiences, little by little, into the network couplings of
the brain. When the neural pattern matches the totality (meaningfulness)
its information potential disappears. On top of this, there is in the
fetus a continuous growth of new neurons, which have to be connected to
the network. As a result of these processes, the outside world is, at
least partly, synchronized with the inside, mental world. Eureka, the
baby finally begins to think and exist! In other words, the baby records
changes against a background of synchronized inputs.
* see "existence centrism" in Demand for Resources for a discussion about a shrinking god and the almighty human!
The Category of the Uniquely Human (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
A
main difficulty in formulating the concept of consciousness is our
pride (presumably we should have been equally proud as mice) and our
strong belief in "something uniquely human." However, if we try to
follow the die-hard determinists, we would probably find free will and
destiny easier to cope with, and also that the concept of "the unique
human being" is rather a question of point of view. Following this line
of thought, I suggest turning to old Berkeley as well as to Ryle but
excluding Skinnerian Utopias. Those who think the word determinism
sounds rude and blunt can try to adorn it with complexity to make it
look more chaotic. Chaos here means something you cannot overview no
matter how deterministic it might be. We seem to like complexity just
because we cannot follow the underlying determinism. Maybe the same is
to be said of what it really is to be a human? A passion for
uncertainty, i.e. life itself. Francis Crick in The Astonishing
Hypothesis: "... your sense of personal identity and free will are in
fact no more than the behavior of a vast assembly of nerve cells and
their associated molecules."
This statement is easy to agree on,
so let me continue with another, perhaps more useful, quote from Crick:
"Categories are not given to us as absolutes. They are human
inventions." I think these two statements create an efficient basis for
further investigations into the mystery of thinking. Hopefully you will
forgive me now as I'm going to try to abolish not only the memory but
also the free will and consciousness all together. Then, I will go even
one step further to deny that there are any thoughts (pictures,
representations, etc.) at all in the cortex. At this point, many might
agree, particularly regarding the cortex of the author of this text.
The
main problem here is the storage of memories, with all their colors,
smells, feelings and sounds. Crick suggests the dividing of memory into
three parts: episodic, categorical and procedural. While that would be
semantically useful, I'm afraid it would act more like an obstacle in
the investigation of the brain, because it presupposes that the hardware
uses the same basis of classification and, like a virus, hence infects
most of our analyses.
Nerves, Loops and "Meetputs" (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
According
to Crick, "each thalamic area also receives massive connections from
the cortical areas to which it sends information. The exact purpose of
these back connections is not yet known." In the following paragraphs, I
will outline a hypothetical model in line with this question. The
interpretation of the interface between brain and its surrounding as it
is presented here has the same starting point as Crick's theory but
divides thinking into a relay/network system in the cortex and the
perception terminals (or their representatives in the thalamus) around
the body like an eternal kaleidoscope. Under this model, imagination
would be a back-projected pattern of nerve signals, equal to the
original event that caused them but with the signals faded. This view
suggests that there are not only inputs and outputs but also "meetputs,"
i.e., when an input signal goes through and evolves into other signals
in the cortex, these new signals meet other input signals in the
thalamus.
There is no limit to the possible number of patterns in
such a system, and there is no need for memory storage but rather,
network couplings. These "couplings," or signals, are constantly running
in loops (not all simultaneously but some at any given moment) from the
nerve endings in our bodies through the network in the cortex and back
again to the thalamus. Of course the back-projected signals have to be
discriminated from incoming signals, thereby avoiding confusion
regarding fantasy and reality. But this process, though still unknown,
could be quite simple and perhaps detected simply by the direction where
it comes from. As a consequence of the loops, the back-projected
pattern differs from the incoming signals, or the stimuli. Therefore,
every signal from the body, perceptions, hormonal signals and so on,
either finds its familiar old routes or patterns of association in the
network (established experiences) or creates new connections (new
experiences) that can be of varying durability. For example, if someone
is blind from the moment of birth, he or she will have normal neuronal
activity in the cortex area of vision. On the other hand, in case of an
acquired blindness, the level of activity in the same area will become
significantly lower over time. This is logical according to the EMAH
model because, in the former case, the neurons have never become
involved in association patterns of vision but were engaged in other
tasks. In the latter case, the neurons have partly remained in previous
vision patterns, which are no longer in use, while the rest has moved
onto other new tasks.
It is important to note that human
thinking, contrary to what today's computers do, involves the
perceptions that originate from the chemical processes in the body's
hormonal system, what we carelessly name "emotions." This, I think, is
the main source behind the term "human behavior". The difference between
man and machine is a source of concern but, as I see it, there is no
point in making a "human machine". But perhaps someone might be
interested in building a "human-like machine".
Body vs. Environment - a History of Illusions (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
According
to the EMAH model, its nerves define our body. This view does not
exactly resemble our conventional view of the human body. Thus, our
hormonal signals inside our body, for example, can be viewed (at least
partially) as belonging to the environment surrounding the EMAH-body.
The meaning of life is to uphold complexity by guarding the borders and
it is ultimately a fight against entropy. In this struggle, life is
supported by a certain genetic structure and metabolism, which
synchronizes its dealings with the surrounding environment. Balancing
and neutralizing these dealings is a job done by the nerves.
A
major and crucial feature of this "body-guarding" mechanism is knowledge
of difference in the directions between incoming signals and outgoing,
processed signals. On top of this, both areas change continuously and
thus have to be matched against each other to uphold or even improve the
complexity. According to this model, people suffering from
schizophrenia, just like healthy people, have no problem in
discriminating between inputs and outputs. In fact, we can safely assume
that the way they sometimes experience hallucinations is just like the
way we experience nightmares. Both hallucinations and nightmares seem so
frightening because they are perceived as incoming signals and confused
as real perceptions. The problem for the schizophrenic lies in a defect
in processing due to abnormal functions in and among the receptors on
the neurons, which makes the association pattern unstable and "creative"
in a way that is completely different compared with controlled
fantasies. In the case of nightmares, the confusion is related to low
and fluctuating energy levels during sleep. A frightful hallucination is
always real because it is based on perceptions. What makes it an
illusion is when it is viewed historically from a new point of view or
experienced in a new "now," i.e., weighed and recorded as illusory from a
standpoint that differs from the original one. In conclusion, one can
argue that what really differentiates a frightful ghost from a harmless
fantasy is that we know the latter being created inside our body,
whereas we feel unsure about the former.
EMAH Computing as Matched Changes (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
EMAH
does not support the idea that information is conveyed over distances,
both in the peripheral and central nervous systems, by the times of
occurrence of action potentials?
"All we are hypothesizing is
that the activity in V1 does not directly enter awareness. What does
enter awareness, we believe, is some form of the neural activity in
certain higher visual areas, since they do project directly to
prefrontal areas. This seems well established for cortical areas in the
fifth tier of the visual hierarchy, such as MT and V4." (Crick &
Koch, 1995a,b). Hardware in a computer is, together with software
(should be “a program” because this word signals programming more
directly), specified at the outset. A high level of flexibility is made
possible through the hardware's ability to unceasingly customize to
incoming signals. This is partly what differs human beings from a
machine. The rest of the differentiating factors include our perceptions
of body chemistry such as hormones, etc. Programming a computer
equipped with flexible hardware, i.e., to make them function like
neurons, will, according to the EMAH-model, make the machine resemble
the development of a fetus or infant to a certain extent. The
development of this machine depends on the type of input terminals.
All
input signals in the human, including emotional ones, involve a
feedback process that matches the incoming signals from the environment
with a changing copy of it in the form of representations in the brain's
network couplings. Life starts with a basic set of neurons, the useful
connections of which grow as experiences come flooding in. This complex
body of neuronal connections can be divided into permanent couplings,
the sum of experiences that is your "personality," and temporary
couplings, short-term "memories" for everyday use.
A certain
relay connection, if activated, results in a back-projected signal
toward every receptor originally involved and thus creates, in
collaboration with millions of other signals, a "collage" that we often
call awareness. This is a constant flow and is in fact what we refer to
as the mysterious consciousness. At this stage, it is important to note
that every thought, fantasy or association is a mix of different kinds
of signals. You cannot, for example, think about a color alone because
it is always "in" or "on" something else (on a surface or embedded in
some kind of substance) and connected by relay couplings to other
perceptions or hormonal systems. "Meaning" is thus derived from a
complex mix of the loops between perceptions and back-projected
perceptions. This can be compared to a video camera system with a
receiving screen and a back-projecting screen. The light meter is the
"personality" and the aperture control the motor system. However, this
system lacks the complex network system found in the cortex and thus has
no possibility to "remember." The recorded signal is of course not
equivalent to the brain's network couplings because it is fixed. To save
"bytes," our brains actually tend to "forget" what has been
synchronized rather than remember it. Such changes in the brain (not
memories) are what build up our awareness. This process is in fact a
common technique in transmitting compressed data.
Short-Term Memories and Dreams (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
At
any given moment, incoming signals, or perceptions, have to be
understood through fitting and dissolving in the net of associations. If
there are new, incomprehensible signals, they become linked (coupled)
to the existing net and localized in the present pattern of
associations. Whether their couplings finally vanish or stay depends on
how they fit into the previous pattern and/or what happens next.
As
a consequence of this coupling process, memories in a conventional,
semantic meaning do not exist, because everything happens now.
Consciousness or awareness is something one cannot influence, but
rather, something that involves an ongoing flow of information to and
from nerve endings through the brain (a relay station). For every given
moment (now), there is consequently only one possible way of acting. One
cannot escape awareness or decisions because whatever one thinks, it is
based on the past and will rule the future. Memories are thus similar
to fantasies of the future, based on and created by experiences.
Regarding short-term memory, I agree with Crick's view and hypothesis.
But I certainly would not call it memory, only weaker or vanishing
couplings between neurons. Remember that with this model, the
imagination of something or someone seen a long time ago always has to
be projected back on the ports were it came through and thus enabling
the appropriate association pattern. Although signals in each individual
nerve are all equal, the back-projected pattern makes sense only as a
combination of signals. The relay couplings in the cortex is the "code",
and the receptor system is the "screen." Because this system does not
allow any "escape" from the ever changing "now" which determines the
dealings with the surrounding environment. Living creatures are forced
to develop their software by living.
Dreams are, according to
this model, remains of short-term memories from the previous day(s),
connected and mixed with relevant association patterns but excluding a
major part of finer association structures. This is why dreams differ
from conscious thinking. The lack of finer association structures is due
to low or irregular activity levels in the brain during sleep. The
results are "confused thoughts", which are quite similar to those of
demented people, whose finer neural structures are damaged because of
tissue death due to a lack of appropriate blood flow. Thus dreams are
relevantly structured but in no way a secret message in the way
psychoanalysts see them, whereas patients with dementia tend to go back
to their childhood due to the irrevocable nature of the physical
retardation process. Investigating dreams and their meanings by
interpreting them is essentially the same as labelling them as
psychological (in a psychoanalytical sense). A better and less biased
result would emerge if the researcher actually lived with the subject
the day before the dream occurred. Rather than analyzing pale and almost
vanished childhood experiences from a view trapped in theoretical
prejudices that describe an uncertain future, the researcher should
perhaps put more effort in the logic of the presence.
Donald Duck and a Stone in the Holy Land of Language (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
Wittgenstein:
"Sie ist kein Etwas, aber auch nicht ein Nichts!" (Phil. Untersuch.
304). Also see P. Klevius' analysis of a stone (in Demand for Resources -
on the right to be poor, 1992).
Although Wittgenstein describes
language as a tool it seems more appropriate to classify it as human
behavior. Unlike tools language is a set (family) of a certain kind of
bodily reactions (internal and/or towards its environment). We have to
reject, not only the grammar which tries to force itself on us, but
also, and perhaps even more so, representations we, without any
particular reason, assign to language.
Language is basically
vocal but apart from that little has been said about its real
boundaries. One could actually argue that the best definition is perhaps
the view that language is a human territory. The question whether
animals have a language is then consequently meaningless. On the other
hand, Wittgenstein denied the existence of a "private language" because
applying it could never prove the validity of its products. We are
trapped in words and connotations of language although these categories
themselves, like language in general, are completely arbitrary "language
games", as Wittgenstein would have put it. (no offense, Mr Chomsky and
others, but this is the tough reality for those trying to make sense of
it in the efforts of constructing intelligent, talking computers).
Furthermore, these categories change over time and within different
contexts with overlapping borders.
Changing language games
provide endless possibilities for creating new "language products", such
as e.g. psychodynamic psychology. I believe this is exactly what
Wittgenstein had in mind when he found Freud interesting as a player of
such games but with nothing to say about the scientific roots of the
mental phenomenon. Let's image Donald Duck and a picture of a stone.
Like many psychological terms, Donald Duck is very real in his
symbolized form but nonetheless without any direct connection to the
reality that he symbolizes. In this sense, even the word stone has no
connection to the reality for those who don't speak English. Words and
languages are shared experiences.
It is said that a crucial
feature of language is its ability to express past and future time. This
might be true but in no way makes language solely human. When bees
arrive to their hive they are able, in symbolic form, to express what
they have seen in the past so that other bees will "understand" what to
do in the future. Naming this an instinct just because bees have such an
uncomplicated brain does not justify a different classification to that
of the human thinking. If, as I proposed in Demand for Resources
(1992), we stop dividing our interactions with the surrounding world in
terms of observation and understanding (because there is no way of
separating them), we will find it easier to compare different human
societies. By categorization, language is an extension of
perception/experience patterns and discriminates us as human only in the
sense that we have different experiences. Words are just like
everything else that hits our receptors. There is no principle
difference in thinking through the use of words or through sounds,
smells (albeit not through thalamus), pictures or other "categories."
Ultimately, language is, like other types of communication with the
surrounding world, just a form of resistance against entropy.
To
define it more narrowly, language is also the room where psychoanalysis
is supposed to live and work. A stone does not belong to language, but
the word "stone" does. What is the difference? How does the word differ
from the symbolic expression of a "real" stone in front of you? Or if we
put it the other way round: What precisely makes it a stone? Nothing,
except for the symbolic value derived from the word "stone." The term
"observation" thus implicates an underlying "private language". When
Turing mixed up his collapsing bridges with math, he was corrected by
Wittgenstein, just as Freud was corrected when he tried to build
psychological courses of events on a basis of natural science.
Wittgenstein's "no" to Turing at the famous lecture at Cambridge hit
home the difference between games and reality.
Archetypes and
grammar as evolutionary tracks imprinted in our genes is a favorite
theme among certain scholars. But what about other skills? Can there
also be some hidden imprints that make driving or playing computer games
possible? And what about ice hockey, football, chess, talk shows, chats
and so on? The list can go on forever. Again, there is no
distinguishing border between evolutionary "imprints" and other
stimulus/response features in ordinary life.
"Primitive" vs. "Sophisticated" Thinking (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
The
more synchronized (informed) something or someone is with its
surrounding reality, the less dynamics/interest this something or
someone invests in its relationship with that particular reality.
Interest causes investment and social entropy excludes investment
economy because economy is always at war against entropy. The key to
economical success is luck and thus includes lack of knowledge. No
matter how well a business idea is outlined and performed, the success
or lack of success is ultimately unforeseeable. In Demand for Resources
(1992) I discussed the possibility of some serious prejudice hidden in
Karl Poppers' "top achievement of civilization", namely the "World 3"
and his and Eccles' assumption of an increasing level of sophistication
from the primitive to the modern stage of development. It is of course
easy to be impressed by the sophistication of the artificial, technical
environment constructed by human, including language and literature,
etc. But there is nonetheless a striking lack of evidence in support of a
higher degree of complexity in the civilized human thinking than that
of e.g. Australian Aboriginals, say 25,000 years ago. Needless to say,
many hunting-gathering societies have been affluent in the way that they
have food, shelter and enough time to enrich World 3, but in reality
they have failed to do so.
Even on the level of physical
anthropology, human evolution gives no good, single answer to our
originality. What is "uniquely human" has rested on a "gap," which is
now closed, according to Richard Leakey and Roger Lewin, among others.
This gap is presumably the same as the one between sensory input and
behavioral output mentioned above.From an anthropological point of view,
it can be said that a computer lacks genetic kinship, which, however,
is a rule without exception in the animate world, although we in the
West seem to have underestimated its real power.
Deconstructing the Mind (copyright P. Klevius 1992-2004)
A
deconstruction of our underlying concepts of the brain can easily end
up in serious troubles due to the problem with language manipulation.
Wittgenstein would probably have suggested us to leave it as it is. If
language is a way of manipulating a certain area - language - then the
confusion will become even greater if we try to manipulate the
manipulation! But why not try to find out how suitable "the inner
environment" is for deconstruction? After all, this environment
presupposes some kind of biology at least in the border line between the
outside and the inside world. Are not behavioral reactions as well as
intra-bodily causes, e g hormones etc. highly dependent on presumed
biological "starting points"? How does skin color or sex hormones affect
our thinking? Where do causes and reactions start and isn't even the
question a kind of explanation and understanding?
Determinists
usually do not recognize the point of free will although they admit the
possible existence of freedom. Why? Obviously this needs some
Wittgensteinian cleaning of language. Unfortunately I'm not prepared for
the task, so let's pick up only the best looking parts, i.e. that words
as freedom, will, mind, etc., are semantic inventions and that they
have no connections to anything else (i.e. matter) if not proved by
convincing and understandable evidence. Does this sound familiar and
maybe even boring? Here comes the gap again. Stimuli and response seen
purely as a reflex is not always correct, says G. H. von Wright, because
sometimes there may be a particular reason causing an action. According
to von Wright, an acoustic sensation, for example, is mental and
semantic and thus out of reach for the scientific understanding of the
body-mind interaction. Is this a view of a diplomatic gentleman eating
the cake and wanting to keep it too? To me, it is a deterministic
in-determinist's view.
G. H. von Wright concludes that what we
experience in our brain is the meaning of its behavioral effects. In
making such a conclusion that it is rather a question of two different
ways of narrowing one's view on living beings von Wright seems to narrow
himself to Spinoza's view. Is meaning meaningful or is it perhaps only
the interpreter's random projection of himself or herself? Is it, in
other words, based only on the existence of the word meaning?
Aristotle
divided the world primarily into matter and definable reality (psyche).
As many other Greek philosophers, Aristotle was an individualist and
would have fitted quite well in the Western discourse of today.
Berkeley, who was a full-blood determinist, however, recognized the
sameness in mind and matter and handed both over to "god". Consequently
Philonous' perceived sensations in the mind were not aligned with Hylas'
view of immediate perceptions. We thus end up with Berkeley as a
spiritual die-hard determinist challenging materialistic humanism.
Conclusion
In
conclusion one might propose a rethinking of the conventional hierarchy
of the brain. What we used to call "higher levels", perhaps because
they are more pronounced in humans, are in fact only huge "neural
mirrors" for the real genius, thalamus (and its capability of two-way
communication with extensions in the cerebellum, spine, nerve ends etc),
i.e. what has sometimes been interpreted as part of the "primitive"
system. In other words, one may propose a view describing the "gap"
between humans and animals as a quantitative difference in the
amount/power of cerebral "mirroring" and communication with thalamus,
rather than as a distinct qualitative feature. Nothing, except our
"emotions", seems to hinder us from making a "human machine". And
because these very "emotions" are lived experiences (there is, for
example, no way to scientifically establish what could be considered
"emotions" in a fetus) nothing, except the meaninglessness in the
project itself, could hinder us from allowing a machine to "live" a
"human life".
Comments
Post a Comment